White Supremacy Is Not an Illness

*Co-Authored by Christopher Petrella and Justin Gomer

Protest against desegregation. Photo: Library of Congress.
Protest against desegregation, Little Rock, Arkansas, 1959. Photo: Library of Congress.

A few weeks ago, we convened and moderated a “justice and equity” reading group for students, staff, and faculty at a local college. Our inaugural meeting centered on an essay in which the author calls attention to the shortcomings of organizing racial justice interventions in higher education around the sanitized and depoliticized language of “diversity.”

While nearly every participant agreed that programs and initiatives captured under the banner of “diversity” would fail to remediate historical and contemporary racial wrongs, we quickly noticed something else: a number of white discussants began describing racism as a “disease,” as a “mental illness,” and as a form of “deviant behavior.” In a private conversation after the gathering, one staff member approached us with the suggestion that we should consider “lobotomizing the racists that hold our country back.”

The subtext was palpable: racism is little more than a behavior-based psychopathology that discloses itself in discrete manifestations of bigotry, prejudice, and misunderstanding. According to such a construction, racism can only be treated with medical intervention. Racial inequity, therefore, is simply the sum of the actions of individual bigots and racial justice can be achieved by “curing” those individuals.

The presumption that one can eliminate racism by snuffing out a few “bad apples” misses the mark. In fact, such a paradigm misdiagnoses the systemic and ideological production of race itself which is squarely centered in white supremacy.

The “racism as disease” paradigm only seems to make sense if one were also to believe that racism is 1) a matter of (mis)recognition and (mis)perception meted out in an apolitical and behaviorist colorblind present; 2) an unfortunate holdover from slavery, a past mistake that has yet to be rectified; and 3) an anomaly; a radical deviation from the telos of dominant political institutions and practices.

51usxkzfdcl-_sy344_bo1204203200_

Such a psychopathological paradigm, however, is not an appendage of nineteenth century scientific racism but rather twentieth century liberal social science. In An American Dilemma: The Negro Problem and Modern Democracy (1944), Swedish Nobel-Laureate economist Gunnar Myrdal argued that “[racism] is a terrible and inexplicable anomaly stuck in the middle of our liberal democratic ethos.” His popular study—funded by the Carnegie Foundation—provides a forceful, if incomplete, framework for explaining the persistence of racial injustice in the United States. Myrdal’s book quickly became an authoritative text for defenders of racial integration in the postwar period and his work gained popularly in the U.S. imagination after it was cited in Brown v. Board of Education (1954).

Together, Myrdal’s study and the Brown decision helped to shift race discourse away from systemic critiques of white supremacy emblematized by DuBois’s The Souls of Black Folk (1903) to diagnoses based on “psychological knowledge” and personal attitudes. Addressing and eliminating quantifiable racial inequities gave way to treating individual racists (i.e. the few “bad apples”) in an otherwise racially just country. Structural white supremacy, in other words, became conflated with individual bigotry.

screen-shot-2016-12-11-at-5-56-31-pm
Google Books Ngram tracking usage of “white supremacy” and “racism” from 1900-2008. Source: Google.

Consider the Google Books Ngram depiction above. From 1900 to the mid-century, the terms “white supremacy” and “racism” were both used at a similar rate in popular and scholarly usage. Beginning in the late 1950s, however, “racism” began to surpass “white supremacy” as the preeminent term for marking, diagnosing, and ameliorating various forms of racial injustice. The deficiency of this term rests in its ability to invisibilize both its locus and its origin: whiteness. Avoiding the term “white” overlooks the policies, practices, and hierarchies of domination and exclusion that has shaped U.S. and global history.

Myrdal’s study continues to set the parameters of mainstream race discourse in the United States. His anomaly thesis casts racism in the vernacular of deviance and abnormality, providing the discursive basis for thinking about racism as illness or disease.

White supremacy, however, is unexplainable by the anomaly thesis. In School Desegregation (1984) scholar Jennifer Hochschild rightly argues that “racism is not simply an excrescence on a fundamentally healthy liberal democratic body…Liberal democracy and racism in the U.S. are historically, even inherently, reinforcing; American society as we know it exists only because of its foundation in racially based slavery, and it thrives only because racial discrimination continues. The apparent anomaly is an actual symbiosis.” White supremacy is not an unfortunate, anomalous stain on an otherwise virginal tapestry of democracy but rather, to paraphrase Hannah Arendt, it’s terribly, terrifyingly normal.

Mrs. Nettie Hunt explaining to her daughter the meaning of the decision banning school segregation. Photo: Library of Congress, Prints and Photographs Division.
Mrs. Nettie Hunt explaining to her daughter the meaning of the decision banning school segregation (Photo: Library of Congress).

In fact, the American Psychiatric Association (APA) has for decades admitted that racial injustice is too normal to be considered a mental illness or a disease. In 1969, a group of black psychiatrists urged the organization to acknowledge that racism is the “major mental health problem of this country” and to include extreme bigotry as a recognized mental illness in the Diagnostics and Statistics Manual (DSM). Though the APA endorsed the “general spirit of reform and redress of racial inequities in American psychiatry” it rejected the psychiatrists’ desire to classify extreme bigotry as a mental illness. In order for racism to be considered a mental illness, the APA declared, racism must deviate from normative behavior. Because racism is ubiquitous, it could not constitute a mental illness. The APA used this rationale to keep racism out of the DSM in 1980, 1987, 1994, and 2013.

The ideology of race itself leads back to whiteness and white supremacy. U.S. immigration and naturalization legislation, race-based marriage statutes, inheritance law, redlining, and the segregation of public facilities are all examples of how whiteness informs policy and practice. They draw, secure, police, and legitimize the parameters of whiteness and non-whiteness.

So-called anti-miscegenation statutes reinforce this argument. From a strictly etymological perspective “anti-miscegenation” most closely refers to a proscription against “race-mixing” in marriage or conjugal entanglements. The term, however, does not accurately depict the ideological underpinnings of the law. Most anti-miscegenation laws, in fact, did not prohibit marriage or sexual relations between two non-white people. What architects of anti-miscegenation laws feared most was race-mixing between white and non-white people because such a social practice would compromise the prospect of white racial purity, white national purity, and global white supremacy. Similarly, U.S. naturalization law from 1790 to 1952 carried with it an explicit prerequisite of whiteness. For instance, the first U.S. Immigration and Naturalization law (1790) restricted naturalized citizenship to “a free white [male], who shall have resided within the limits and under the jurisdiction of the United States for the term of two years.”

Ultimately, framing white supremacy as exceptional, individualized, and through the language of disease obscures its origins and movements. As George Lipsitz argues, “Whiteness has a cash value” that produces advantages and “profits” for white people in virtually all areas of social organization including housing, education, employment, and intergenerational wealth. Lipsitz continues, “white supremacy is usually less a matter of direct, referential, and snarling contempt than a system for protecting the privileges of whites by denying communities of color opportunities for asset accumulation and upward mobility” and access to full and legitimate citizenship.

Those who continue to explain racial injustice through appeals to disease or illness implicitly reinforce a discourse that misdiagnoses the machinations of white supremacy. If we are truly to craft an antiracist politics capable of threatening the endurance of white supremacy, we must reject analyses and interventions that individualize social injustice by relying on notions of disease, mental illness, or deviance.


Christopher Petrella is a Lecturer in American Cultural Studies at Bates College. His work explores the intersections of race, state, and criminalization. He completed a Ph.D. in African Diaspora Studies from the University of California, Berkeley. Follow him on Twitter @CFPetrella.

Justin Gomer is an Assistant Professor of American Studies at California State University, Long Beach. His work centers on race and representation in the post-civil rights era. He completed a Ph.D. in African Diaspora Studies from the University of California, Berkeley.

Share with a friend:
Copyright © AAIHS. May not be reprinted without permission.

Comments on “White Supremacy Is Not an Illness

  • Avatar

    Watering down the language from “white supremacy” to “racism” to “diversity,” and suggesting white supremacy is mental illness is tantamount to the victor of war being the one who gets to write the history. The narrative continues to be usurped, to their advantage, by white people.

  • Avatar

    Thank you for a much-needed discussion. Your approach intersects with another recent perspective: https://www.aaihs.org/implicit-bias-and-american-history/

    We look forward to more interdisciplinary analysis that frames racism across multiple academic fields. It is needed.

  • Avatar

    While I agree that racism cannot be reduced to a “disease” or “mental illness,” that it is in fact much “more than a behavior-based psychopathology that discloses itself in discrete manifestations of bigotry, prejudice, and misunderstanding,” I would think that such a view is perfectly compatible with attempts to understand the social-psychological mechanisms whereby notions of “white supremacy” and racist beliefs become part of the worldviews (individuated as ‘lifeworlds’) and ideologies of individuals and groups. In other words, we should endeavor to understand the dialectical relations between psychic structure and social structure that help us understand why _these_ individuals and _those_ groups are racist, while other individuals and groups are (largely) free of such beliefs.

    By way of an (in part) analogical and historical exemplum I would cite the work of the early Freudo-Marxists (settings aside for now the differences between individuals—say, for example, Reich and Fromm—within this orientation) who sought to fashion the somewhat crude methods of a nascent psychoanalytic social psychology into tools that could help us explain the possible sundry reasons for the rise of fascism and its corresponding virulent species of anti-semitism (which of course had Christian origins of long-standing). So, for example, the provocative notion of “social character” (as an ‘ideal type’) was used by Fromm to account for dominant forms and patterns of assimilation and socialization in society, owing to prevailing political and economic conditions in conjunction with particular historical-cultural factors. Fromm and his fellow researchers at the Frankfurt School made a pioneering study of the Weimar working-class so as to discern possible correlations (any causal theories would require further research and elaboration) between class affiliation, party membership or affinity, and “psychological type.” One of the conclusions the study reached is that for a surprising number of workers surveyed, avowed allegiance to left or left-leaning political parties and sentiment often went hand-in-hand with an “authoritarian” character-type. Fromm summarized the study’s results:

    “’the most important result is the small proportion of left-wingers who were in agreement in both thought and feeling with the socialist line.’ Only 15 percent had ‘the courage, readiness for sacrifice, and spontaneity needed to rouse the less active and overcome the enemy.’ Thus the actual strength of leftist anti-Nazi parties was much less than met the eye.”

    Or, in the words of Wolfgang Bonss, “Fromm’s conclusion was that despite all the electoral successes of the Weimar Left, its members were not in the position, owing to their character structure, to prevent the victory of National Socialism.” In short, many of the workers were all-too-willing to support the fascists when push came to shove, manifest political attitudes be damned.

    Of course today we have more positivist-oriented research from cognitive psychology in addition to psychoanalytic social psychology (which I view as a non-positivist ‘science of subjectivity’ in the first instance) along post-Freudian Marxist lines by way of social scientific explanation and understanding. These approaches are not the same as, nor can they be reduced to reliance on biomedical conceptions of individual and group mental illness, although they have been used to bolster the claim that entire societies can be “sick” or (with hyperbole) “insane” (hence the locution: ‘pathology of normalcy’) insofar as they fail to meet the basic material and existential needs of their members, needs that are essential to human growth, individuation, and self-realization.

    I have two bibliographies with titles that amount to several powerful arguments for the relevance of psychology to social scientific explanation: Marxism and Freudian Psychology: https://www.academia.edu/27926885/Marxism_and_Freudian_Psychology_bibliography
    and Philosophy, Psychology, & Methodology for the Social Sciences: https://www.academia.edu/19449832/Philosophy_Psychology_and_Methodology_for_the_Social_Sciences_A_Select_Bibliography (of course not all of the titles in the latter compilation are about the possible relevance role of psychology in social scientific explanation).

  • Avatar

    didn’t Herbert Blumer say basically the same thing in 1958?
    Race Prejudice as a Sense of Group Position
    The Pacific Sociological Review, Vol. 1, No. 1 (Spring, 1958), pp. 3-7

    “Unfortunately, this customary way of viewing race prejudice
    overlooks and obscures the fact that race prejudice is
    fundamentally a matter of relationship between racial
    groups. A little reflective thought should make this very
    clear. Race prejudice presupposes, necessarily, that racially
    prejudiced individuals think of themselves as belonging to
    a given racial group. It means, also, that they assign to
    other racial groups those against whom they are prejudiced.
    Thus, logically and actually, a scheme of racial identification
    is necessary as a framework for racial prejudice.”

  • Avatar

    I wrote an article on my blog addressing this issue. It’s a good discussion to have. White supremacy has to be properly defined and diagnosed so that it is understood. The link is below…

    “I make the argument that white supremacy has been normalized since the slavery era and at times codified in laws…but it is not a normal state of mind. I don’t believe people are born racist with hatred in their hearts. I believe people are indoctrinated into a pathologically mental social construct based upon racial dominance at a very young age. A system designed by white supremacists and maintained by suspected white supremacists seeking to maintain a debunked, scientifically-ignorant system of racial manipulation and control.”

    https://blackandintellectual.com/blog/is-white-supremacy-a-social-psychopathology

Comments are closed.